L'era dell'interlegalità
DOI: 10.1401/9788815370334/c17
Notably, most of these treaties
– even those concluded under the auspice of the UNEP – developed in a piecemeal
fashion, tackling each environmental problem separately as it grasped public attention
[15]
. As a result, most environmental agreements, including those addressing
interconnected environmental issues, developed in isolation from each other,
¶{p. 470}often leading to “duplication of effort, lack of
coordination, and even conflict between different environmental regimes”
[16]
. Overall, as a result of such incremental treaty-making, there are
presently more than one thousand multilateral environmental agreements
[17]
, making international environmental law the most “congested” and
possibly, the most fragmented branch of international law
[18]
.
The fragmentation of
international environmental law is further exacerbated by the fact that each MEA can
be characterized as a “legality” or a regime of its own, being equipped with
autonomous institutional structures and procedures to ensure their further development
[19]
. In fact, almost each of one thousand MEA normally establishes a
permanent plenary body, a secretariat, together with numerous advisory bodies and
technical expert groups
[20]
. The plenary bodies – commonly referred to as “Conference of the
Parties” (COP) – serve as a continuous forum for adoption of amendments to the
existing framework treaty or conclusion of new related treaties, usually in the form
of protocols or annexes
[21]
. To complicate the issue even further, the newly developed protocols
often establish their own separate plenary organs, normally called the “Meeting of
the Parties”, which at times do not have the same membership as the respective COP
[22]
. Indeed, following this process, many MEAs, including the 1985 Ozone
Convention, the 1987 Montreal Protocol or the ¶{p. 471}1992
Framework Convention on Climate Change have developed into complex regulatory
regimes, comprising several additional protocols, numerous amendments and additional
decisions by COPs
[23]
. Indeed, the transpiring picture of environmental governance has been
defined as “polycentric”, comprising multiple regime complexes, defined as
“functionally overlapping institutions that continuously affect each other’s operations”
[24]
.
As should become clear from the
description above, this highly-decentralized institutional structure of
international environmental law represents a fertile soil for recurring
inter-legality situations, where several regimes simultaneously regulate the same
subject matter. To illustrate with just one example, both the climate change regime
– represented by the UN Framework Convention on Climate Change (UNFCCC) and its
Kyoto Protocol – and the Convention on Biological Diversity (CBD), address the issue
of forests, albeit from different perspectives
[25]
. The former focuses on the role of forests in mitigating global warming
by viewing them as carbon sinks or, alternatively, as a source of carbon emissions.
To elaborate, since the main goal of the climate change regime is to encourage
parties to reduce emissions, in practice, it gives more value to young trees and
plants, which can act as effective carbon sinks by absorbing large amounts of carbon
dioxide throughout their lifespans
[26]
. Instead, aged trees, that have already accumulated considerable amount
of carbon, are seen as less valuable or potentially troublesome as they will
eventually discharge ¶{p. 472}the carbon back to the atmosphere when
they die and decompose
[27]
. Seen in this light, several scholars argued that replacing the old
forests with industrial plantations of young fast-growing trees, capable of
isolating more carbon, is a preferable option from the climate change perspective
[28]
. This stance, however, comes into conflict with the objectives of the
biodiversity regime that seeks to protect the forest ecosystem holistically, by
maintaining the balance between young and old plant lives
[29]
. As a result, the parties to both the UNFCCC and the CBD are placed
under inconsistent obligations under the two related agreements, potentially
disincentivizing them to fulfill their environmental obligations under either of the agreements
[30]
.
The problem of multiple sources
overlapping in uncoordinated manner is further intensified by the fact that most of
environmental regimes have weak compliance mechanisms in the form of reporting
duties, essentially leaving it to the parties themselves to decide upon which of the
competing obligations should be honored
[31]
. To clarify, out of more than thousand environmental agreements, only
very few provide for some forms of judicial settlement mechanisms and those that do
are rarely used
[32]
. As a result, the majority of contemporary environmental litigation
takes place through non-environmental institutions, including human rights courts,
as the next sections will demonstrate. And it is in this dimension that the second
external inter-legality profile of international environmental law becomes
visible.¶{p. 473}
2.2. External Inter-legality: The Relationships Between International Environmental Law And Human Rights Law
Despite the absence of a
central focal point in international environmental law, it is hardly disputed that
the discipline represents an autonomous branch of international law, underpinned by
common principles and regulatory standards
[33]
. This autonomous nature of environmental law becomes even more evident
when it comes into interaction with other branches of international law, thereby
creating “external” inter-legality situations. This section will address one of such
inter-legality situations, namely the relationships between international
environmental law and human rights law.
Although – as demonstrated in
the previous section – international environmental law has developed as a separate
regime with its own principles and institutions, its relationship with human rights
law, for a long time, has been perceived as one of synergy and increasing integration
[34]
. Given the past achievements of human rights in improving human
condition worldwide, as well as the natural link between human rights and
environment, environmental issues, from the very beginning, have been viewed through
the human rights paradigm
[35]
. In other words, the objectives of the two regimes have been long
understood as corresponding, being both focused on improving the human well-being
[36]
. This approach to environmental protection was pioneered by the 1972
Stockholm Declaration on the Human Environment, which as the first principle,
proclaimed the “fundamental ¶{p. 474}right to freedom, equality, and
adequate conditions of life, in an environment of a quality that permits a
life of dignity and well-being”
[37]
. As clear from the title and the wording of the Declaration, the
document put environmental protection at the service of human interests, with the
former being understood as an indispensable precondition for the enjoyment of human rights
[38]
. Although the Stockholm Declaration was not a legally binding
instrument, it has been extremely influential in the normative framing of the
relationships between the environment and human rights
[39]
. As noted by Fatma Zohra Ksentini, the former UN Special Rapporteur on
Human Rights and the Environment, the document constituted a “qualitative leap”,
which turned the ethos of environmental law from environmental protection to that of
“a right to a healthy and decent environment”
[40]
. This subsumption of environmental law within the logic of the human
rights regime was further exacerbated by the “implementation deficit” of
international environmental law outlined above: in absence of its own judicial
mechanisms, environmental claims have been increasingly adjudicated by human rights
courts and predominantly within this instrumental paradigm
[41]
.
However, this narrow reading of
environmental law as merely instrumental to human needs has been challenged by a
number of environmental scholars and policy-makers, who sustain that it “ultimately
reduces all non-human aspects of
¶{p. 475}the ecosystem to
consideration of their short-term economic value to humanity, exacerbating resource
over-exploitation and environmental deterioration”
[42]
. Instead, the proponents of the opposing “intrinsic” approach to
environmental protection argue that the ultimate goal of environmental law is the
protection of the nature as a whole, understood as an end-goal in itself
[43]
. This approach is explicit in several environmental law instruments,
including the 1982 Word Charter of Nature, which in its preamble declares that
“every form of life is unique, warranting respect regardless of its worth
to a man”
[44]
. Another illustration of this approach is the 1979 Bern Convention on
the Conservation of European Wildlife and Natural Habitats, which proclaims that
“wild flora and fauna constitute a natural heritage of (…) intrinsic
value that needs to be preserved and handed on to future generations”
[45]
. On this line of thought, humans are viewed as an interdependent part of
a composite global ecosystem, vested with the duties to protect its other
components, irrespective of the their utility or economic benefits to the human race
[46]
. In other words, although this intrinsic approach to environmental
protection – currently dominating the scholarship – also acknowledges that the
protection of the global ecosystem is the primary interest of the humankind being
linked to its survival, it stresses the higher purpose of preserving the environment
for the sake of present and future generations, in contrast to the utilitarian
approach outlined above
[47]
. {p. 476}
Note
[15] See H. van Asselt, Managing the Fragmentation of International Environmental Law: Forestation at the Intersection of Climate and Biodiversity Regimes, in «New York University Journal of International Law and Politics», 44, 2012, pp. 1205 ff., 1209.
[16] D. Bodansky, The Art and Craft of International Environmental Law, Cambridge, Harvard University Press, 2010, p. 35.
[17] See J. Brunnee, Environment, Multilateral Agreements, in Max Planck Encyclopedia of International Law (last accessed on 5 February, 2021), par. 3.
[18] The term “treaty congestion” was famously coined by E. Brown Weiss in Id., International Environmental Law: Contemporary Issues and the Emergence of a New World Order, in «Georgetown Law Journal», 81, 1993, pp. 675 ff., 697.
[19] See Birnie, Boyle and Redgwell, International Law and the Environment, cit., p. 84.
[20] See Brunnee, Environment, Multilateral Agreements, parr. 24-30.
[21] See ibidem, par. 24
[22] See ibidem, par. 25.
[23] See Birnie, Boyle and Redgwell, International Law and the Environment, cit. p. 85. For comprehensive overview of environmental governance as a whole, see ibidem, pp. 58-105.
[24] K.N. Scott, The Dynamic Evolution of International Environmental Law, in «Victoria University of Wellington Law Review», 49, 2018, pp. 607 ff., 622-623.
[25] For a comprehensive discussion, see van Asselt, Managing the Fragmentation of International Environmental Law, cit.
[26] See J.C. Morgan III, Fragmentation of International Environmental Law and the Synergy: A Problem and A 21st Century Model Solution, in «Vermont Journal of Environmental Law», 18, 2016, pp. 134 ff., 139.
[27] See ibidem.
[28] See van Asselt, Managing the Fragmentation of International Environmental Law, cit., p. 1232.
[29] See ibidem, pp. 1224-1228, especially 1225; Morgan III, Fragmentation of International Environmental Law and the Synergy, cit., p. 139.
[30] See Morgan III, Fragmentation of International Environmental Law and the Synergy, cit., p. 140.
[31] See Brunnee, Environment, Multilateral Agreements, cit., parr. 43-46.
[32] See Kotzé and Daly, A Cartography of Environmental Human Rights, cit., p. 1049.
[33] See T. Stephens, Multiple International Courts and the Fragmentation of International Environmental Law, in «Australian Yearbook of International Law», 25, 2006, pp. 227 ff., 236-242.
[34] See M. Petersmann, Narcissus’ Reflection in the Lake: Untold Narratives in Environmental Law Beyond the Anthropocentric Frame, in «Journal of Environmental Law», 30, 2018, pp. 235 ff., 241-249.
[35] See Kotzé and Daly, A Cartography of Environmental Human Rights, cit., pp. 1049-1051.
[36] See D. Shelton, Human Rights, Environmental Rights, and the Right to Environment, in «Stanford Journal of International Law», 28(1), 1991, pp. 103 ff., 104.
[37] Stockholm Declaration of the United Nations Conference on the Human Environment (16 June 1972), UN Doc. A/Conf.48/14/Rev 1 (1973), Principle 1. For discussion, see Petersmann, Narcissus’ Reflection in the Lake, cit., pp. 243-244.
[38] See ibidem, p. 243; Shelton, Human Rights, Environmental Rights, and the Right to Environment, cit., p. 112.
[39] For an overview, see Petersmann, Narcissus’ Reflection in the Lake, cit., pp. 244-249.
[40] F.Z. Ksentini, UN Special Rapporteur on the Human Rights and Environment, Final Report on Human Rights and Environment, 6 July 1994, E/CN.4/Sub.2/1994/9, p. 23, as cited in Petersmann, Narcissus’ Reflection in the Lake, cit., p. 248.
[41] See Kotzé and Daly, A Cartography of Environmental Human Rights, cit., p. 1049.
[42] Shelton, Human Rights, Environmental Rights, and the Right to Environment, cit., p. 109.
[43] See ibidem, p. 104.
[44] World Charter for Nature (28 October 1982), UN General Assembly Resolution, A/Res/37/7. On this, see also Petersmann, Narcissus’ Reflection in the Lake, p. 244; cit., D. Shelton, Human Rights, Environmental Rights, and the Right to Environment, cit., p. 109.
[45] Convention on the Conservation of European Wildlife and Natural Habitats (19 September 1979), Europ. T.S. No. 104, preamble. See also Shelton, Human Rights, Environmental Rights, and the Right to Environment, cit., p. 109.
[46] See ibidem, p. 110.
[47] See ibidem. Indeed, as explained by Shelton, the intrinsic approach is also anthropocentric in nature as it ultimately acknowledges that the protection of ecosystem is necessary for the survival of mankind. This type of anthropocentrism, however, should be distinguished from utilitarianism, which only protects non-human aspects of ecosystem for their economic utility or other short-term benefits to the mankind.